From Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 6: Barad’s Ethico-onto-epistemology

Context:

In this report we present our concluding thoughts after having read the chapters 1, 2, 5, 6 & 8 of Karen Barad’s “Meeting the Universe Halfway”. In these chapters, she explains her notion of ethico-onto-epistemology pulling together insights gained from quantum physics and the fact that our practices literally ‘matter’ (hence: New Materialism). The way we got here was in first reading Bergson’s “Time and Free Will” (see report here) to then see how Bergson’s initial challenge to psychophysics morphed into the Einstein-Bergson debate on the primacy of physics over philosophy (see report here). We then read A.N. Whitehead’s “Process and Reality” to see another principled objection to a classical-corpuscular view of mechanistic physics as the ideal scientific and philosophical view (see report here). His more holistic interpretation of the universe based on physico-mathematical interpretations (known as ‘process philosophy’) is largely ignored in contemporary analytic philosophy but serves as direct inspiration to many contemporary thinkers across scientific disciplines. Although Barad does not explicitly make reference to him, it proved worthwhile to contrast Whitehead’s thinking with that of N. Bohr (see report here). Bohr’s philosophy-physics is – for Barad – the foundation of her ethico-onto-epistemological analysis in chapters 3, 4 & 7. She argues that the epistemological lesson of Bohr needs to be extended to its ontological implications (see report here). What remains then is the link to the ethical analysis that is a fil rouge – a background motif, if you will – with all of the thinkers mentioned before. It’s also a link between quantitative insights (as in quantum physics) and qualitative insights gained from studying the lived experience (as in gender, disability and culture studies).

Barad – the conclusive:

For us there is no question Barad in fact succeeds in entangling the insights from quantum physics with those based on discursivity as discussed by Foucault and Butler’s analysis of performativity. This means that the simplistic ideas of, on the one hand, a deterministic and exact scientific view of the universe and, on the other hand, the idea of social construction ‘through-and-through’ are to be abandoned definitively. Instead, we need to accept that the actual (agential) realist view is one wherein our practices make a literal material difference. As agents or actors in this world we do not remain unmoved but, in moving, we also do not leave the world unmoved. In science we are therefore not looking for some isolated matter or some isolated practice that, on analysis, can give a definite explanation of phenomena. No, in science we’re concerned with a, necessarily indeterminate, dynamic of phenomena that produce a world in which we (humans and nonhumans) live together. While we cannot fully determine this intra-action, we are accountable for what happens since we do have a choice to exclude or include others by the practices we adopt.

Here we have added – to the epistemological and ontological dimensions discussed in our previous session – the beginning of an ethical dimension by linking the themes of quantum physical indeterminacy with the themes of (acceptance of) diversity in gender, disability as well as cultural studies. This is done by replacing the dominant exact scientific metaphor of reflection and representation by the new metaphor of diffraction and production. The latter indeed emerged from the discussion of quantum physics as an unavoidable element (this mirrors themes independently taken up by Bergson and Whitehead) in contrast to notions of exact science that, sticking with a Newtonian deterministic worldview, want to eliminate this element as a mere ‘disturbance’. 

As said above, whilst we differ on whether all aspects of Barad’s analysis succeed, we do agree that the above conclusion is unavoidable: given there is unavoidably an element of entanglement or diffraction in science (as in any practice), science comes with impacts on our world that cannot be disentangled from what happens in that world. In Barad’s words – science ‘matters’ and therefore it matters what we do in science (and how we do it)..

Barad – the inconclusive:

For us there is also no question that there is more work to do on how this specifically does matter from an ethical point of view. The examples in ‘Meeting The Universe Halfway’ are, in our view, not concrete enough to provide actual guidance for instance in the field of our project: neurodevelopmental disorders. 

Maybe the reason why it stays a little too abstract in connecting with ethical concerns is a consequence of laying too much focus on diffraction and disregarding the complementary aspect of reflection. Maybe (see also the discussion on humanism vs posthumanism in the previous report) this leads to a loss of connection to the typically ethical questions of doing justice to a specific other. These are interesting angles also suggested by previous reading but probably it matters less to study these angles in a very abstract way given what we’re missing is a connection to the very concrete of ethical practices in the here and now or the you and me. At least in our discussion, we spontaneously geared towards the question of how science matters and, in light of the above, what a good scientific practice is. 

A call for intra-action:

So, we end this reading club with a desire to produce something that builds on the reading we have done: a way to argue that – contrary to the received opinion in the modern West – science without experience is simply unscientific. This probably requires us to make more precise how quantitative and qualitative methods combine to form good science (maybe in the way that Oliver Sacks’ efforts to give people with a neurodevelopmental disorder their own voice was critical in unleashing scientific advance in this field). We believe this would be a worthwhile bridge between New Materialism and more conventional views of science and ethics, an intra-action bringing scientists and scholars in the different disciplines closer instead of digging ever deeper terminological trenches.

From Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 5: The difference between Barad and Bohr

Context:

We finally arrived at the destination of our Book club’s journey: Karen Barad’s “Meeting the Universe Halfway”. The way we got here was reading Bergson’s “Time and Free Will” (see report here) to then see how Bergson’s initial challenge to psychophysics morphed into the Einstein-Bergson debate about the primacy of physics over philosophy (see report here). We then stopped over at A.N. Whitehead’s “Process and Reality” to see another principled objection to a classical-corpuscular view of mechanistic physics as the ideal scientific and philosophical view (see report here). His more holistic interpretation of the universe based on physico-mathematical interpretations (known as ‘process philosophy’) is largely ignored in contemporary analytic philosophy but serves as direct inspiration to many contemporary thinkers across scientific disciplines. Although Barad does not explicitly make reference to him, it proved worthwhile to contrast Whitehead’s thinking with that of N. Bohr (see report here). Indeed, the philosophical ideas of Bohr are the starting point of Barad’s Meeting the Universe Halfway and Whitehead as well as Bohr developed their ideas in explicit contrast with those of Einstein. Small wonder then that the same respectful criticism of Einstein is a fil rouge in Barad who, herself a quantum physicist, takes up the philosophical implications of  physics which have proven so counterintuitive for deterministic thinking. As it is a quite massive book giving rise to a lot of intra-acting (see how dogeared it is) we split the debate in two. In this penultimate session we talk about her interpretation of quantum physics (the chapters 3, 4, 7). In the next (final) one we conclude by looking at the ethical ramifications she distills out of this interpretation (ethics is a common theme across all these thinkers!).

Barad on Bohr – the agreement:

Bohr’s ‘philosophy-physics’ is the starting point for Barad. She first disentangles it in a very meticulous way from the ‘uncertainty’ reading which is probably most well known from the like-named principle proposed by Heisenberg. Instead, according to us quite rightly so, it is argued that Bohr preferred the term ‘indeterminacy’ as this captured the lesson of quantum physics more accurately. Indeed, it is not that there is something determined in spacetime that we cannot measure without disturbing it, i.e. without uncertainty. Rather, Bohr’s idea of complementarity holds that there’s no such determined thing prior to (or separate from) our observation of it. Instead, the fact revealed by quantum physics is that, when we observe a quantum phenomenon, we need to make a choice on how we want to observe it. It is this choice that allows us to determine the phenomenon either as to its object characteristic (its position) or as to its wave characteristics (its momentum). These two complementary ways of observing it require two different, and mutually exclusive, experimental arrangements. In this way the very idea of physics as deterministics, so preferred by Einstein, is no longer a tenable position (as Barad, specifically in chapter 7 explains with reference to experiments that could not be carried out in Bohr’s time but have been carried out in the meantime).

As the below picture tries to illustrate, this puts Barad and Bohr very far removed from the contemporary Western consensus assuming that a scientific explanation needs ultimately to be grounded by concept of an isolated particular or individual. In this her analysis is to a large extent on the same wavelength as that of Whitehead who, as we saw before, started from the non-separability of phenomena based on the image of wave propagation. This is far removed from the current Western consensus, with its view of the particular importance of the thought of a conscious individual human being. This is illustrated by both Whitehead and Bohr emphasizing affinity of their philosophy and science with Eastern thought.

That said, Barad also explicitly says she wants to go further than Bohr. Maybe fittingly, this is also where our discussion group started disagreeing. This, hopefully productive, debate is summarized in the next section but before we switch to that I complete the discussion of the above picture by stating that Barad’s view emphasizes (see Whitehead’s starting point) the entangled nature of nature. As she herself says, the title Meeting the Universe Halfway is not about taking a kind of middle position in the way Bohr can be interpreted. No, she is clearly taking diffraction as the ultimate truth revealed by quantum physics.

Barad on Bohr – the disagreement:

We can be brief about the disagreement of Barad and Bohr (hence about us disagreeing in our discussion). The basic issue Barad has with Bohr is that he limited his official lesson to a lesson of epistemology (how we can know nature) where she argues his argument leads to a straightforward ontological conclusion (how nature is). For Barad, philosophy-physics as proposed by Bohr should not be limited to the way we, humans, obtain knowledge but it should be seen as the generic way in which phenomena come to matter. This allows her to introduce her key concept of intra-agency within phenomena connecting epistemology not only to ontology but also to ethics. The limit of human knowledge which Bohr self-imposed on himself is then a remnant of a humanism that still makes humans to be too exceptional a species in our world.

We disagreed on whether this extension of Bohr’s epistemological lesson is correct and – relatedly –  whether his self-avowed humanism indeed restricts his ethical outlook to one in which the human species is the be all and end all of nature. Luckily, we have one session left to see whether we can find agreement based on our previous readings where, as said above already, ethical questions always lurked in the background. Whatever else we might find of Barad, she clearly has the merit of putting these questions front and center in a bold way within a principled discussion of contemporary advances in scientific knowledge! 

To be continued – humanism vs. posthumanism:

Next time, and this will be the coronation of this specific book club, we therefore start with specifical ethical questions that motivated the NeuroEpigenEthics project. This will bring us to the issues why ‘New Materialist’ views are critically important in no longer separating of issues of a scientific/materialistic and an ethics/diversity nature. We will read the remaining chapters of Meeting The Universe Halfway that make a connection between interpretation of (quantum) physics and ethical theorizing (a connection that all of the thinkers discussed in this book club endorse in one way or the other). We will then see whether the humanism of Bohr is indeed incompatible with the insights of contemporary continental thought such as for instance developed in posthumanism. Or whether we can find some “golden middle” ground where we can all meet after all.

The NeuroEpigenEthics Family meets: Prof. Eva Jablonka

Unfortunately, Coronavirus required us to cancel our yearly team meeting where we would have been so very happy to welcome Prof. Eva Jablonka, one of the pioneers in epigenetic research and theorizing. Fortunately we had the opportunity of discussing her work online with her on the 5th of May 2020. We specifically focused on the book she wrote together with Prof. Marion Lamb: Evolution in Four Dimensions (2nd edition, 2014). It was a most lively discussion where the neurological and, mainly, the ethical were prominently present. We provide a very short reflection belo

w but not without first thanking all the friends of the NeuroEpigenEthics team who joined the discussion showing the value of interdisciplinary thinking: Luca Chiapperino (Science and Technology Studies, University Lausanne), Wim Van Daele (anthropologist, University Agder), Wim Vanden Berghe (microbiologist, University of Antwerp) and Sander Van de Cruys (experimental psychologist, University of Leuven). Covid-19 may keep us in a physical bubble, we remain determined to continue breaking academic bubbles!

We dug right in with a question on whether epigenetic effects should always be framed in the negative. The answer of Prof. Jablonka was as balanced as her work on evolution: she was not in favor of claiming epigenetics as the be all and end all of all science. She sees it rather as an additional tool in a truly transdisciplinary toolkit. On the one hand, we have to consider that there is a lot of unpredictability in epigenetic effects. A lack of stress following a ‘good’ lifestyle may well stabilize problematic effects while some stress triggers plasticity that enables learning and discovering better solutions. On the other hand, as is the core of the ideas in Evolution in Four Dimensions epigenetics really is the crossroads of biological and cultural drivers of evolution. As worked out in the paper Cultural Epigenetics (Jablonka 2016) this means one always has to consider, at least, these 2 perspectives. The example given was very much à propos the NeuroEpigenEthics mission: one can look at ADHD as a problem for which some microbiological cure is to be found, or one can look at it socially as an affordance opening up new potential. Biology has a place in both perspectives, but it will, in the second perspective, focus more on something Richard Lewontin called “meta-plasticity”. This perspective will avoid trying to fix things from a point of view of current standards and allow to be more open to creative opportunities evolution affords in creating new potential.

This discussion naturally led to a question on relation between epigenetics and normative issues. Prof. Eva Jablonka here first drew attention to the application of Waddington’s landscape metaphor (Waddington 1957) to the social dimension. A norm can in this metaphor be seen as a strong attractor canalizing the development of organism in a direction of what are ‘stable social arrangements’. In work she co-authored (Tavory, Jablonka and Ginsburg 2012) it is explained how for instance poverty can be self-perpetuating until some change (as fortunately has happened to some extent with feminism and homosexuality) to some of the key stabilizers takes root. Unfortunately, only a case-by-case interdisciplinary study of the broad epigenetic landscape can help to identify how to uproot oppressive stabilizers so no simplifying messages here. Still we can see that there always is a dynamic between the individual change agents and some level of collective responsibility (see our discussion on Iris Marion Young for a helpful way of conceptualizing this dynamic!). Again, epigenetics is not saying things are cast in stone but rather that wherever there is canalization there are, always also, permeable boundaries allowing evolutionary plasticity to overthrow attractors.

This use of the Waddingtonian metaphor invited a long discussion on how to understand it, and specifically how to understand interactions between the genetic and social dimensions as well as the possibilities for change afforded to individual agency. Prof. Eva Jablonka did in this discussion refer to the paper she and Noble published recently (2019) in which they tried (see photograph below) to extend the metaphor to show this interaction. In it, the lower pegs are the genes as per Waddington’s original drawing but the top parachute shows the social and environmental influence on development. This allows to visualize that we aren’t just canalized by our biology but that if we change social circumstances we can – and do – have an impact on this development. Feminism and queer studies in this way have had an impact on the development outlook of more than half of the world’s population although as regards poverty we clearly have much more to do to destabilize the dynamics.

A snapshot from our discussion: on the right the adaptation of Waddington’s landscape as per Jablonka and Noble (2019), on the left Eva Jablonka, Kristien Hens (University Antwerp), Luca Chiapperino (University Lausanne) and Sander Van de Cruys (University of Leuven). 

Our discussion went on for three hours and still there was much more to be said. Not only on the visualization of the epigenetic landscape (how to depict the complementary aspects of plasticity and canalization that were already the focus of Waddington’s original work) but also on how to translate these insights into the clinical and bioethical discourse, where the simplicity of the ‘traditional’ genetic model is still a very strong attractor for patients as well as clinicians. So we left it as a To Be Continued, grateful for Prof. Eva Jablonka’s time and happy that these are the very questions we pursue in our project. The last word we give to our guest: “The dynamic of stability always comes together with a dynamics of change.”

Jo Bervoets

References:

Jablonka, Eva. 2016. “Cultural Epigenetics.” The Sociological Review Monographs. https://doi.org/10.1002/2059-7932.12012.

Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. 2014. “Evolution in Four Dimensions.”, MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9689.001.0001.

Jablonka, Eva, and Denis Noble. 2019. “Systemic Integration of Different Inheritance Systems.” Current Opinion in Systems Biology. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.coisb.2018.10.002.

Tavory, Iddo, Eva Jablonka, and Simona Ginsburg. 2012. “Culture and Epigenesis: A Waddingtonian View.” Oxford Handbooks Online. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195396430.013.0031.

Waddington, Conrad Hall. 1957. “The Strategy of the Genes”. London: Allen & Unwin.

From Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 4: Bohr and/vs. Whitehead

Context:

We started our journey towards Karen Barad’s “Meeting the Universe Halfway” by reading Bergson’s “Time and Free Will” (see report here). We then saw Bergson’s initial challenge to psychophysics morphing into the Einstein-Bergson debate about the primacy of physics over philosophy (see report here). We saw that Bergson was not the only one contesting a classical-corpuscular view of mechanistic physics as the ideal for science (and, therefore, philosophy). We discussed A. N. Whitehead’s proposal (see report here) of a more holistic interpretation of the universe based on physico-mathematical interpretations. Although this ‘process philosophy’ was largely ignored in contemporary analytic philosophy, it serves as direct inspiration to a lot of contemporary thinkers outside of that tradition. Our last stop will be dedicated to the philosophical ideas of Niels Bohr explicitly discussed in Karen Barad’s Meeting the Universe Halfway. Bohr also contrasted his ideas explicitly with those of Einstein which made it interesting to look at (the many) alignments and (some) discrepancies of his views, as founding father of quantum physics with the philosophy proposed by Whitehead.

Read moreFrom Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 4: Bohr and/vs. Whitehead

From Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 3: Whitehead’s relational alternative

Context:

We started our journey towards Karen Barad’s “Meeting the Universe Halfway” by reading Bergson’s “Time and Free Will” (see report here). We then saw Bergson’s initial challenge to psychophysics morphing into the Einstein-Bergson debate about the primacy of physics over philosophy (see report here). From a contemporary, modern Western, point of view it was Einstein’s point of view that prevailed, so entrenching the classical-corpuscular view of mechanistic physics as the ideal science (and therefore philosophy) should strive for. Such a view was however not only contested by Bergson but in his own way by A. N. Whitehead who thereby inspired contemporary thinkers such as Donna Haraway. We were fortunate enough to get introduced to Whitehead by Ronny Desmet (author of the Stanford Encyclopedia entry on him). Although Whitehead is almost erased from the history of analytic philosophy, his approach was of a thoroughly mathematical and physicist nature and at the same time embraced elements of Eastern philosophy. As shown in the picture of a letter by Whitehead, he directly interacted with Einstein and, whilst in Harvard, was mentor of many leading analytic philosophers like Quine. Therefore he may well be pivotal in controversies between the current philosophical traditions. In the following we provide a short reflection on this session. After this we’ll have one session on the interpretation of quantum physics by Whitehead and Bohr. This makes us well prepared for our final goal of an informed discussion of Karen Barad’s Meeting the Universe Halfway.

Read moreFrom Bergson over Bohr to Barad Session 3: Whitehead’s relational alternative